The Separation between State and Religion

In time we will realize that Democracy is the entitlement of individuals to every right that was in its times alloted to kings. The right to speak and decide, to be treated with decency, to serve and be served by people in a State of “love” that is, to serve with one’s work for the development of ‘life’. To belong to the Kingdom of Human Beings without racial, national, social or academic separations. To love and be loved. To die at the service of the whole and be honored in one’s death, for one’s life and work was legitimately valued. To be graceful and grateful. To have the pride and the humility of being One with the Universe, One with every realm of Existence, One with every living and deceased soul. To treat with dignity and be treated with dignity for One is dignified together with All others and Life itself. To walk the path of compassion, not in the sorrow of guilt but in the pride of being. To take responsability for one’s mistakes and sufferings and stand up again and again like a hero and a heroine and face the struggle that is put at one’s feet and in one’s hands. Millions of people, millions and millions of people might take many generations to realize the consciousness of our humaneness but there is no other dignified path for the human being.

The “work” as I conceive it is psychological and political. Psychology is the connection between the different dimensions within one’s self and Politics is the actualization of that consciousness in our practical lives. Religion is the ceremony that binds the connectedness between the individual and the Universe. The separation between religion, politics and science, the arts and sports is, in the sphere of the social, the reflection of the schizophrenia within the individual and the masses. The dialogue between individuality and the "human" belongs to consciousness. The tendency to develop cults resides in the shortcomings we’are finding in life as it is structured today. “Life” has become the private property of a few priviledged who cannot profit from it because as soon as it is appropriated it stops to be “life” or “life-giving”.

We are all the victims of our own invention and each one is called upon to find solutions. The only problem is believing our selves incapable of finding them. We are now free to use all Systems of knowledge objectively, sharing them without imposing our will on each other. To become objective about our lives means to understand that the institutions that govern its experience are critically important. That we are one with the governments, one with the religious activities that mark its pace, that the arena’s in which we move our bodies and the laboratories in which we explore our possibilities are ALL part and parcel of our own personal responsibility. That WE ARE ONE WITH EACH OTHER AND EVERYTHING AROUND US and acknowledge for ourselves a bond of love in conscious responsibility. That we human beings know ourselves part of each other and are willing and able to act on our behalf for the benefit of each and every individual. That we no longer allow governments, industries, universities or any other institution to run along unchecked by the objective principles of humaneness. That we do not allow gurus to abuse their power or governors to steal the taxes and use them to their personal advantage in detriment of the whole. That we do not allow abuse from anyone anywhere because life is too beautiful to do so and that we are willing to stop the rampant crime with the necessary compassion Conscious knowledge is every individual's right. Conscious action is every individual's duty.

Blog Archive

Sunday 23 May 2010

Ton- Elena and Natural Law- Hobbes and positivism


1. ton - May 23, 2010 [Edit]

gee elena, before you closed the previous page i thought you had finally come to some type of practical resolution, that you were done with projecting your “visciousness” onto me, that maybe you could move on from this ‘viscious circle’ you are trapped in, the pattern of lashing-out at “the other” in anger. i had hope that you’d finally grasped what i’ve been ‘saying’ to you for some time now, something about which we — that’s you and i, elena — both seemed to agree on toward the end of the previous page: that you, elena, need to help yourself before you can begin to presume to help others. i thought you finally “got the message” because you stopped your pattern of directing your vitriolic visciousness and anger toward me, i thought, i hoped (for your sake) that maybe you had moved on from this pattern of behavior, that you’d finally resolved to help yourself…. but then apparently you felt the overwhelming compulsion to attack me again before you closed-out the previous page. now i ask you elena: who is stuck in a “viscious circle” ? who ? that would be you elena, i am only entering into your viscious circle here in an attempt to help you to recognize it and to break free… but apparently this is going to take a long time and a lot of patience. you may remember that once upon a time on the fofblog i quoted an old saying from my country when i ‘said’ to you: “not with a ten foot pole elena” — meaning that i realized then that you were a real “case” and i didn’t want to get entangled in your mess… well since then i realized something about the genuine difficulty your are experiencing, after all i too went through a process of cult-recovery, and i thought you might be helped through it with my intervention and suggestions… but it appears that you consider yourself to be above and beyond being helped… that level of hubris, that level of arrogance may be your biggest obstacle to realizing “wholeness” within yourself, elena, rather than searching for it externally through the “WE” and “US” myopia.
that little turd you left on the previous page was a manifestation of the compulsion you feel to perpetuate your own “viscious circle” a pattern of behavior you refuse to acknowledge. i know you do sense the viscious circle you are trapped in, but you fail to recognize it IN YOURSELF by projecting it onto “the other” (in this case it happens to be “ton”). i guess some things don’t change, or at least some things with you change very, very slowly… by the end of the previous page it seemed like maybe the light was coming on a glimmer for you, just a little bit, that maybe you were finally getting the point… oh well, two steps forward, three steps back… but keep trying elena, what choice do you have after all…?
for the sake of clarity, and in a continuing effort to remind you of the ‘unconscious’ effects and manifestations of projection, i encourage you to take a good hard look at this turd you left elena, and to start cleaning up your mess by withdrawing projections and to realize that everything you ‘say’ here is a reflection of your own mentality, you could be looking in the mirror and ‘saying’ every word here to yourself and it would be absolutely true and accurate about YOU. here’s a good exercise for you elena, print your post (below) on a piece of paper – i encourage you to do this exercise with all your writing before you consider posting – take the printed words and stand before a mirror, read it aloud and everytime you say the word “YOU” and “YOUR” take a moment to stop, look at yourself in the mirror and reflect these thoughts back on the source from which they issue forth — that is, your self — to make it a little easier i will capitalize the words for you here:
e: “Just before I leave this page I want to make sure that what I said to YOU is clear.
What I find extremely boring is the vicious circle in which YOU have become fixed and that is what I find so uninteresting about YOU. It is as if YOUR electric self were in a short circuit and could not encompass the whole no matter how many connections are given to YOU to expand your perceptions.
Since I believe we are changing beings, I hope YOU can move from that viciousness someday and continue to participate from a more interesting circuitry of YOUR self.
For the time being, I wish YOU good luck.”
~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Yyg86ucrQrA
~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~
and maybe this will help you to understand your preoccupation with the “WE” ism that has so captivated your mentality — see “participation mystique” for your further researches:
“Another term for the phenomenon of projection is participation mystique. Like projection, a person or group of people can unwittingly place themselves under a spell. This so-called spell can be anything: an idea, person, or thing. One becomes so preoccupied that one’s own sense of self is momentarily taken up by the object of obsessive interest.
Group Identification Occurs: examples of a person or groups of persons under the spell of participation mystique occur when one person or a group is so under the spell that anyone who does not agree with their idea might be seen as a threat. This can occur in all areas of life. Another word for this phenomenon is “projective identification. How and why does this strange phenomenon exist?”
http://www.jungiananalyticpraxis.com/projection_lecture.htm
~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~
i would wish you luck but being dependent upon luck is not going to take the place of actually doing the practical, real work you have before you…

2. Elena - May 23, 2010 [Edit]

Thanks Ton, the mirror works both ways and I’m wonderfully busy with other work that you have no interest in, so allow me to continue my research.
Have a great day!

3. Elena - May 23, 2010 [Edit]

The following could enlighten our conversation.
Natural law or the law of nature (Latin: lex naturalis) is a purported law whose content is set by nature and that therefore has validity everywhere.[1] The phrase natural law is opposed to the positive law (which is man-made) of a given political community, society, or nation-state, and thus can function as a standard by which to criticize that law.[2] In natural law jurisprudence, on the other hand, the content of positive law cannot be known without some reference to the natural law (or something like it). Used in this way, natural law can be invoked to criticize decisions about the statutes, but less so to criticize the law itself. Some use natural law synonymously with natural justice or natural right (Latin ius naturale), although most contemporary political and legal theorists separate the two.
Natural law theories have exercised a profound influence on the development of English common law,[3] and have featured greatly in the philosophies of Thomas Aquinas, Francisco Suárez, Richard Hooker, Thomas Hobbes, Hugo Grotius, Samuel von Pufendorf, John Locke, Francis Hutcheson, Jean Jacques Burlamaqui, and Emmerich de Vattel. Because of the intersection between natural law and natural rights, it has been cited as a component in United States Declaration of Independence and the Constitution of the United States. The essence of Declarationism is that the founding of the United States is based on Natural law.
Contents [hide]
1 History
1.1 Aristotle
1.2 Stoic natural law
1.3 Christian natural law
1.4 Islamic natural law
1.5 Hobbes’ natural law
1.6 Cumberland’s rebuttal of Hobbes
1.7 Liberal natural law
2 Contemporary Catholic understanding
3 In contemporary jurisprudence
4 See also
5 References
6 Further reading
7 External links
[edit]History
The use of natural law, in its various incarnations, has varied widely through its history. There are a number of different theories of natural law, differing from each other with respect to the role that morality plays in determining the authority of legal norms. This article will deal with its usages separately rather than attempt to unify them into a single theory.
[edit]Aristotle
Greek philosophy emphasized the distinction between “nature” (physis, φúσις) on the one hand and “law”, “custom”, or “convention” (nomos, νóμος) on the other. What the law commanded varied from place to place, but what was “by nature” should be the same everywhere. A “law of nature” would therefore have had the flavor more of a paradox than something which obviously existed.[1] Against the conventionalism that the distinction between nature and custom could engender, Socrates and his philosophic heirs, Plato and Aristotle, posited the existence of natural justice or natural right (dikaion physikon, δικαιον φυσικον, Latin ius naturale). Of these, Aristotle is often said to be the father of natural law.[4]
Aristotle’s association with natural law is due largely to the interpretation given to his works by Thomas Aquinas.[5] This was based on Aquinas’s conflation of natural law and natural right, the latter of which Aristotle posits in Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics (Book IV of the Eudemian Ethics). Aquinas’s influence was such as to affect a number of early translations of these passages,[6] though more recent translations render them more literally.[7] Aristotle notes that natural justice is a species of political justice, viz. the scheme of distributive and corrective justice that would be established under the best political community;[8] were this to take the form of law, this could be called a natural law, though Aristotle does not discuss this and suggests in the Politics that the best regime may not rule by law at all.[9]
The best evidence of Aristotle’s having thought there was a natural law comes from the Rhetoric, where Aristotle notes that, aside from the “particular” laws that each people has set up for itself, there is a “common” law that is according to nature.[10] The context of this remark, however, suggests only that Aristotle advised that it could be rhetorically advantageous to appeal to such a law, especially when the “particular” law of one’s own city was averse to the case being made, not that there actually was such a law;[11] Aristotle, moreover, considered two of the three candidates for a universally valid, natural law provided in this passage to be wrong.[1] Aristotle’s theoretical paternity of the natural law tradition is consequently disputed.
[edit]Stoic natural law
The development of this tradition of natural justice into one of natural law is usually attributed to the Stoics. The rise of natural law as a universal system coincided with the rise of large empires and kingdoms in the Greek world.[12] Whereas the “higher” law to which Aristotle suggested one could appeal was emphatically natural, in contradistinction to being the result of divine positive legislation, the Stoic natural law was indifferent to the divine or natural source of the law: the Stoics asserted the existence of a rational and purposeful order to the universe (a divine or eternal law), and the means by which a rational being lived in accordance with this order was the natural law, which spelled out action that accorded with virtue.[1] Stoics emphasized the universal ideas of individual worth, moral duty, and universal brotherhood. These theories became highly influential among Roman jurists, and consequently played a great role in subsequent legal theory.[citation needed]
[edit]Christian natural law
This section needs additional citations for verification.
Please help improve this article by adding reliable references. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (April 2009)
A number (though not all) of the early Church Fathers sought to incorporate it into Christianity. This was true in the West more so than in the East. The most notable among these was Augustine of Hippo, who equated natural law with man’s prelapsarian state; as such, a life according to nature was no longer possible and men needed instead to seek salvation through the divine law and grace of Jesus Christ. In the Twelfth Century, Gratian reversed this, equating the natural and divine laws. Thomas Aquinas restored Natural Law to its independent state, asserting that, as the perfection of human reason, it could approach but not fully comprehend the Eternal law and needed to be supplemented by Divine law. See also Biblical law in Christianity.
According to Thomas Aquinas, all human laws were to be judged by their conformity to the natural law. An unjust law is not a law, in the full sense of the word. It retains merely the ‘appearance’ of law insofar as it is duly constituted and enforced in the same way a just law is, but is itself a ‘perversion of law.’[13] At this point, the natural law was not only used to pass judgment on the moral worth of various laws, but also to determine what the law said in the first place. This could result in some tension.[14]
The natural law was inherently deontological in that although it is aimed at goodness, it is entirely focused on the ethicalness of actions, rather than the consequence. The specific content of the natural law was therefore determined by a conception of what things constituted happiness, be they temporal satisfaction or salvation. The state, in being bound by the natural law, was conceived as an institution directed at bringing its subjects to true happiness. In the 16th century, the School of Salamanca (Francisco Suárez, Francisco de Vitoria, etc.) further developed a philosophy of natural law. After the Church of England broke from Rome, the English theologian Richard Hooker adapted Thomistic notions of natural law to Anglicanism.
[edit]Islamic natural law
The notion of inalienable rights was found in early Islamic law and jurisprudence, which denied a ruler “the right to take away from his subjects certain rights which inhere in his or her person as a human being.” Islamic rulers could not take away certain rights from their subjects on the basis that “they become rights by reason of the fact that they are given to a subject by a law and from a source which no ruler can question or alter.”[15] In addition, early Islamic jurists, from the 8th century to the 16th century, made a distinction between the huquq Allah (“rights of God”) and huquq al-ibad (“rights of individuals”). The former were based on the rights established in the Qur’an and Sunnah, while the latter resembled the concept of natural rights. This arose from the Istislah method, developed in order to deal with new issues that find no clear answer in the sacred religious texts. Many early Islamic jurists thus resorted to “background values concerning inherent qualities of the individual” in order to deal with these issues, incorporating “naturalistic reasoning in their juridical analyses.” They applied the “rights of God” and “rights of individuals” as “an interpretive mechanism to frame their naturalistic assumptions and apply them in legal analysis to create and distribute rights, duties, and public commitments.”[16]
Abū Rayhān al-Bīrūnī, an Islamic scholar and polymath scientist, understood natural law as the law of the jungle. He argued that the antagonism between human beings can only be overcome through a divine law, which he believed to have been sent through prophets. This is also the position of the Ashari school, the largest school of Sunni theology.[17] Averroes (Ibn Rushd), in his treatise on Justice and Jihad and his commentary on Plato’s Republic, writes that the human mind can know of the unlawfulness of killing and stealing and thus of the five maqasid or higher intents of the Islamic sharia or to protect religion, life, property, offspring, and reason. The concept of natural law entered the mainstream of Western culture through his Aristotelian commentaries, influencing the subsequent Averroist movement and the writings of Thomas Aquinas.[18]
The Maturidi school, the second largest school of Sunni theology, posits the existence of a form of natural law. Abu Mansur al-Maturidi stated that the human mind could know of the existence of God and the major forms of ‘good’ and ‘evil’ without the help of revelation. Al-Maturidi gives the example of stealing which is known to be evil by reason alone due to man’s working hard for his property. Killing, fornication, and drinking alcohol were all ‘evils’ which the human mind could know of according to al-Maturidi. The concept of Istislah in Islamic law bears some similarities to the natural law tradition in the West, as exemplified by Thomas Aquinas. However, whereas natural law deems good that which is known self-evidently to be good, according as it tends towards the fulfilment of the person, istislah calls good whatever is connected to one of five “basic goods”. Al-Ghazali abstracted these “basic goods” from the legal precepts in the Qur’an and Sunnah: they are religion, life, reason, lineage and property. Some add also “honour”. Ibn Qayyim Al-Jawziyya also posited that human reason could discern between ‘great sins’ and good deeds.[citation needed]
[edit]Hobbes’ natural law
This law-related article does not cite its references or sources. You can help Wikipedia by including appropriate citations, which can be found through legal research.
By the Seventeenth Century, the Medieval teleological view came under intense criticism from some quarters. Thomas Hobbes instead founded a contractualist theory of legal positivism on what all men could agree upon: what they sought (happiness) was subject to contention, but a broad consensus could form around what they feared (violent death at the hands of another). The natural law was how a rational human being, seeking to survive and prosper, would act. It was discovered by considering humankind’s natural rights, whereas previously it could be said that natural rights were discovered by considering the natural law. In Hobbes’ opinion, the only way natural law could prevail was for men to submit to the commands of the sovereign. Because the ultimate source of law now comes from the sovereign, and the sovereign’s decisions need not be grounded in morality, legal positivism is born. Jeremy Bentham’s modifications on legal positivism further developed the theory.
As used by Thomas Hobbes in his treatises Leviathan and De Cive, natural law is “a precept, or general rule, found out by reason, by which a man is forbidden to do that which is destructive of his life, or takes away the means of preserving the same; and to omit that by which he thinks it may best be preserved.”
According to Hobbes, there are nineteen Laws. The first two are expounded in chapter XIV of Leviathan (“of the first and second natural laws; and of contracts”); the others in chapter XV (“of other laws of nature”).
The first Law of nature is that every man ought to endeavour peace, as far as he has hope of obtaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek and use all helps and advantages of war.
The second Law of nature is that a man be willing, when others are so too, as far forth, as for peace, and defence of himself he shall think it necessary, to lay down this right to all things; and be contented with so much liberty against other men, as he would allow other men against himself.
The third Law is that men perform their covenants made. In this law of nature consisteth the fountain and original of justice… when a covenant is made, then to break it is unjust and the definition of injustice is no other than the not performance of covenant. And whatsoever is not unjust is just.
The fourth Law is that a man which receiveth benefit from another of mere grace, endeavour that he which giveth it, have no reasonable cause to repent him of his good will. Breach of this law is called ingratitude.
The fifth Law is complaisance: that every man strive to accommodate himself to the rest. The observers of this law may be called sociable; the contrary, stubborn, insociable, froward, intractable.
The sixth Law is that upon caution of the future time, a man ought to pardon the offences past of them that repenting, desire it.
The seventh Law is that in revenges, men look not at the greatness of the evil past, but the greatness of the good to follow.
The eighth Law is that no man by deed, word, countenance, or gesture, declare hatred or contempt of another. The breach of which law is commonly called contumely.
The ninth Law is that every man acknowledge another for his equal by nature. The breach of this precept is pride.
The tenth law is that at the entrance into the conditions of peace, no man require to reserve to himself any right, which he is not content should be reserved to every one of the rest. The breach of this precept is arrogance, and observers of the precept are called modest.
The eleventh law is that if a man be trusted to judge between man and man, that he deal equally between them.
The twelfth law is that such things as cannot be divided, be enjoyed in common, if it can be; and if the quantity of the thing permit, without stint; otherwise proportionably to the number of them that have right.
The thirteenth law is the entire right, or else…the first possession (in the case of alternating use), of a thing that can neither be divided nor enjoyed in common should be determined by lottery.
The fourteenth law is that those things which cannot be enjoyed in common, nor divided, ought to be adjudged to the first possessor; and in some cases to the first born, as acquired by lot.
The fifteenth law is that all men that mediate peace be allowed safe conduct.
The sixteenth law is that they that are at controversie, submit their Right to the judgement of an Arbitrator.
The seventeenth law is that no man is a fit Arbitrator in his own cause.
The eighteenth law is that no man should serve as a judge in a case if greater profit, or honour, or pleasure apparently ariseth [for him] out of the victory of one party, than of the other.
The nineteenth law is that in a disagreement of fact, the judge should not give more weight to the testimony of one party than another, and absent other evidence, should give credit to the testimony of other witnesses.
Hobbes’s philosophy includes a frontal assault on the founding principles of the earlier natural legal tradition,[19] disregarding the traditional association of virtue with happiness,[20] and likewise re-defining “law” to remove any notion of the promotion of the common good.[21] Hobbes has no use for Aristotle’s association of nature with human perfection, inverting Aristotle’s use of the word “nature.” Hobbes posits a primitive, unconnected state of nature in which men, having a “natural proclivity…to hurt each other” also have “a Right to every thing, even to one anothers body”[22]; and “nothing can be Unjust” in this “warre of every man against every man” in which human life is “solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short.”[23] Rejecting Cicero’s view that men join in society primarily through “a certain social spirit which nature has implanted in man,”[24] Hobbes declares that men join in society simply for the purpose of “getting themselves out from that miserable condition of Warre, which is necessarily consequent…to the naturall Passions of men, when there is no visible Power to keep them in awe.”[25] As part of his campaign against the classical idea of natural human sociability, Hobbes inverts that fundamental natural legal maxim, the Golden Rule. Hobbes’s version is “Do not that to another, which thou wouldst not have done to thy selfe.”[26]
[edit]Cumberland’s rebuttal of Hobbes
The English cleric Richard Cumberland wrote a lengthy and influential attack on Hobbes’s depiction of individual self-interest as the essential feature of human motivation. Historian Knud Haakonssen has noted that in the eighteenth century, Cumberland was commonly placed alongside Hugo Grotius and Samuel Pufendorf “in the triumvirate of seventeenth-century founders of the ‘modern’ school of natural law.”[27] The eighteenth-century philosophers Shaftesbury and Hutcheson “were obviously inspired in part by Cumberland.”[28] Historian Jon Parkin likewise describes Cumberland’s work as “one of the most important works of ethical and political theory of the seventeenth century.”[29] Parkin observes that much of Cumberland’s material “is derived from Roman Stoicism, particularly from the work of Cicero, as “Cumberland deliberately cast his engagement with Hobbes in the mould of Cicero’s debate between the Stoics, who believed that nature could provide an objective morality, and Epicureans, who argued that morality was human, conventional and self-interested.” [30] In doing so, Cumberland de-emphasized the overlay of Christian dogma (in particular, the doctrine of “original sin” and the corresponding presumption that humans are incapable of “perfecting” themselves without divine intervention) that had accreted to natural law in the Middle Ages.
By way of contrast to Hobbes’s multiplicity of laws, Cumberland states in the very first sentence of his Treatise of the Laws of Nature that “all the Laws of Nature are reduc’d to that one, of Benevolence toward all Rationals.” [31] He later clarifies: “By the name Rationals I beg leave to understand, as well God as Man; and I do it upon the Authority of Cicero.” Cumberland argues that the mature development (“perfection”) of human nature involves the individual human willing and acting for the common good.[32] For Cumberland, human interdependence precludes Hobbes’s natural right of each individual to wage war against all the rest for personal survival. However, Haakonssen warns against reading Cumberland as a proponent of “enlightened self-interest.” Rather, the “proper moral love of humanity” is “a disinterested love of God through love of humanity in ourselves as well as others.”[33] Cumberland concludes that actions “principally conducive to our Happiness” are those which promote “the Honour and Glory of God” and also “Charity and Justice towards men.”[34] Cumberland emphasizes that desiring the well-being of our fellow humans is essential to the “pursuit of our own Happiness.”[35] He cites “reason” as the authority for his conclusion that happiness consists in “the most extensive Benevolence,” but he also mentions as “Essential Ingredients of Happiness” the “Benevolent Affections,” meaning “Love and Benevolence towards others,” as well as “that Joy, which arises from their Happiness.”[36]
[edit]Liberal natural law
This section needs additional citations for verification.
Please help improve this article by adding reliable references. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (April 2009)
Liberal natural law grew out of the medieval Christian natural law theories and out of Hobbes’ revision of natural law, sometimes in an uneasy balance of the two.
Hugo Grotius based his philosophy of international law on natural law. In particular, his writings on freedom of the seas and just war theory directly appealed to natural law. About natural law itself, he wrote that “even the will of an omnipotent being cannot change or abrogate” natural law, which “would maintain its objective validity even if we should assume the impossible, that there is no God or that he does not care for human affairs.” (De iure belli ac pacis, Prolegomeni XI). This is the famous argument etiamsi daremus (non esse Deum), that made natural law no longer dependent on theology.
John Locke incorporated natural law into many of his theories and philosophy, especially in Two Treatises of Government. There is considerable debate about whether his conception of natural law was more akin to that of Aquinas (filtered through Richard Hooker) or Hobbes’ radical reinterpretation, though the effect of Locke’s understanding is usually phrased in terms of a revision of Hobbes upon Hobbesean contractualist grounds. Locke turned Hobbes’ prescription around, saying that if the ruler went against natural law and failed to protect “life, liberty, and property,” people could justifiably overthrow the existing state and create a new one.[37]
While Locke spoke in the language of natural law, the content of this law was by and large protective of natural rights, and it was this language that later liberal thinkers preferred. Thomas Jefferson, arguably echoing Locke, appealed to unalienable rights in the Declaration of Independence, “We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness.”[38]
The Belgian philosopher of law Frank van Dun is one among those who are elaborating a secular conception [1] of natural law in the liberal tradition. However, a secular critique of the natural law doctrine was stated by Pierre Charron in his De la sagesse (1601): “The sign of a natural law must be the universal respect in which it is held, for if there was anything that nature had truly commanded us to do, we would undoubtedly obey it universally: not only would every nation respect it, but every individual. Instead there is nothing in the world that is not subject to contradiction and dispute, nothing that is not rejected, not just by one nation, but by many; equally, there is nothing that is strange and (in the opinion of many) unnatural that is not approved in many countries, and authorized by their customs.”
[edit]Contemporary Catholic understanding
This section needs additional citations for verification.
Please help improve this article by adding reliable references. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (April 2009)
The Roman Catholic Church holds the view of natural law set forth by Thomas Aquinas,[39] particularly in his Summa Theologica, and often as filtered through the School of Salamanca. This view is also shared by some Protestant churches.[40]
The Catholic Church understands human beings to consist of body and mind, the physical and the non-physical (or soul perhaps), and that the two are inextricably linked.[41] Humans are capable of discerning the difference between good and evil because they have a conscience.[42] There are many manifestations of the good that we can pursue. Some, like procreation, are common to other animals, while others, like the pursuit of truth, are inclinations peculiar to the capacities of human beings.[43]
To know what is right, one must use one’s reason and apply it to Aquinas’ precepts. This reason is believed to be embodied, in its most abstract form, in the concept of a primary precept: “Good is to be sought, evil avoided.”[44] St. Thomas explains that:
there belongs to the natural law, first, certain most general precepts, that are known to all; and secondly, certain secondary and more detailed precepts, which are, as it were, conclusions following closely from first principles. As to those general principles, the natural law, in the abstract, can nowise be blotted out from men’s hearts. But it is blotted out in the case of a particular action, insofar as reason is hindered from applying the general principle to a particular point of practice, on account of concupiscence or some other passion, as stated above (77, 2). But as to the other, i.e., the secondary precepts, the natural law can be blotted out from the human heart, either by evil persuasions, just as in speculative matters errors occur in respect of necessary conclusions; or by vicious customs and corrupt habits, as among some men, theft, and even unnatural vices, as the Apostle states (Rm. i), were not esteemed sinful.[45]
However, while the primary and immediate precepts cannot be “blotted out”, the secondary precepts can be. Therefore, for a deontological ethical theory they are open to a surprisingly large amount of interpretation and flexibility. Any rule that helps man to live up to the primary or subsidiary precepts can be a secondary precept, for example:
Drunkenness is wrong because it injures one’s health, and worse, destroys one’s ability to reason, which is fundamental to man as a rational animal (i.e. does not support self preservation).
Theft is wrong because it destroys social relations, and man is by nature a social animal (i.e. does not support the subsidiary precept of living in society).
Natural moral law is concerned with both exterior and interior acts, also known as action and motive. Simply doing the right thing is not enough; to be truly moral one’s motive must be right as well. For example, helping an old lady across the road (good exterior act) to impress someone (bad interior act) is wrong. However, good intentions don’t always lead to good actions. The motive must coincide with the cardinal or theological virtues. Cardinal virtues are acquired through reason applied to nature; they are:
Prudence
Justice
Temperance
Fortitude
The theological virtues are:
Faith
Hope
Charity
According to Aquinas, to lack any of these virtues is to lack the ability to make a moral choice. For example, consider a man who possesses the virtues of justice, prudence, and fortitude, yet lacks temperance. Due to his lack of self control and desire for pleasure, despite his good intentions, he will find himself swaying from the moral path.
[edit]In contemporary jurisprudence
This law-related article does not cite its references or sources. You can help Wikipedia by including appropriate citations, which can be found through legal research.
In jurisprudence, natural law can refer to the several doctrines:
That just laws are immanent in nature; that is, they can be “discovered” or “found” but not “created” by such things as a bill of rights;
That they can emerge by the natural process of resolving conflicts, as embodied by the evolutionary process of the common law; or
That the meaning of law is such that its content cannot be determined except by reference to moral principles. These meanings can either oppose or complement each other, although they share the common trait that they rely on inherence as opposed to design in finding just laws.
Whereas legal positivism would say that a law can be unjust without it being any less a law, a natural law jurisprudence would say that there is something legally deficient about an unjust law. Legal interpretivism, famously defended in the English speaking world by Ronald Dworkin, claims to have a position different from both natural law and positivism.
Besides utilitarianism and Kantianism, natural law jurisprudence has in common with virtue ethics that it is a live option for a first principles ethics theory in analytic philosophy.
The concept of natural law was very important in the development of the English common law. In the struggles between Parliament and the monarch, Parliament often made reference to the Fundamental Laws of England which were at times said to embody natural law principles since time immemorial and set limits on the power of the monarchy. According to William Blackstone, however, natural law might be useful in determining the content of the common law and in deciding cases of equity, but was not itself identical with the laws of England. Nonetheless, the implication of natural law in the common law tradition has meant that the great opponents of natural law and advocates of legal positivism, like Jeremy Bentham, have also been staunch critics of the common law.
Natural law jurisprudence is currently undergoing a period of reformulation (as is legal positivism). The most prominent contemporary natural law jurist, Australian John Finnis, is based in Oxford, but there are also Americans Germain Grisez, Robert P. George, and Canadian Joseph Boyle. All have tried to construct a new version of natural law. The 19th-century anarchist and legal theorist, Lysander Spooner, was also a figure in the expression of modern natural law.
“New Natural Law” as it is sometimes called, originated with Grisez. It focuses on “basic human goods,” such as human life, knowledge, and aesthetic experience, which are self-evidently and intrinsically worthwhile, and states that these goods reveal themselves as being incommensurable with one another.

No comments:

Post a Comment