The Separation between State and Religion

In time we will realize that Democracy is the entitlement of individuals to every right that was in its times alloted to kings. The right to speak and decide, to be treated with decency, to serve and be served by people in a State of “love” that is, to serve with one’s work for the development of ‘life’. To belong to the Kingdom of Human Beings without racial, national, social or academic separations. To love and be loved. To die at the service of the whole and be honored in one’s death, for one’s life and work was legitimately valued. To be graceful and grateful. To have the pride and the humility of being One with the Universe, One with every realm of Existence, One with every living and deceased soul. To treat with dignity and be treated with dignity for One is dignified together with All others and Life itself. To walk the path of compassion, not in the sorrow of guilt but in the pride of being. To take responsability for one’s mistakes and sufferings and stand up again and again like a hero and a heroine and face the struggle that is put at one’s feet and in one’s hands. Millions of people, millions and millions of people might take many generations to realize the consciousness of our humaneness but there is no other dignified path for the human being.

The “work” as I conceive it is psychological and political. Psychology is the connection between the different dimensions within one’s self and Politics is the actualization of that consciousness in our practical lives. Religion is the ceremony that binds the connectedness between the individual and the Universe. The separation between religion, politics and science, the arts and sports is, in the sphere of the social, the reflection of the schizophrenia within the individual and the masses. The dialogue between individuality and the "human" belongs to consciousness. The tendency to develop cults resides in the shortcomings we’are finding in life as it is structured today. “Life” has become the private property of a few priviledged who cannot profit from it because as soon as it is appropriated it stops to be “life” or “life-giving”.

We are all the victims of our own invention and each one is called upon to find solutions. The only problem is believing our selves incapable of finding them. We are now free to use all Systems of knowledge objectively, sharing them without imposing our will on each other. To become objective about our lives means to understand that the institutions that govern its experience are critically important. That we are one with the governments, one with the religious activities that mark its pace, that the arena’s in which we move our bodies and the laboratories in which we explore our possibilities are ALL part and parcel of our own personal responsibility. That WE ARE ONE WITH EACH OTHER AND EVERYTHING AROUND US and acknowledge for ourselves a bond of love in conscious responsibility. That we human beings know ourselves part of each other and are willing and able to act on our behalf for the benefit of each and every individual. That we no longer allow governments, industries, universities or any other institution to run along unchecked by the objective principles of humaneness. That we do not allow gurus to abuse their power or governors to steal the taxes and use them to their personal advantage in detriment of the whole. That we do not allow abuse from anyone anywhere because life is too beautiful to do so and that we are willing to stop the rampant crime with the necessary compassion Conscious knowledge is every individual's right. Conscious action is every individual's duty.

Blog Archive

Monday 31 May 2010

Katrina Jaworski on suicide

http://www.unisa.edu.au/hawkeinstitute/publications/foucault-25-years/jaworski.pdf


Articles like this one are quite amazing for me because they seem to turn over and around quite obvious things and yet, there must be something totally not obvious since Foucault can actually say about suicide that it's the end of power when it is in fact the success of power over the individual. 

But in Foucault's time like in my mother's, the individuals still thought that if they committed suicide, they were giving their great individual affirmation against society, their individualistic "victory" and it was only the confirmation of their defeat! Not that I would "judge" anyone for taking their lives but that I'd argue that no one takes his or her life if they are in a creative process.




Elena 6th Oct 2011
Rereading this article it's clearer what the dilemma for the author is: understanding that there is no such thing as pure individuality and that everything is connected. The premises on which the article is based are not clear but the questioning of the issue is so very worthy. 


One idea I would add and think worth exploring further is that when we talk about the individual we are not talking about individuality, that is, when we talk about and individual we are talking about a "moving being", a moving being in his or her own being, a "changing" being. An individual's "act" is never independent from the whole and the more "original" it seems, the more faithful to the whole it is. The individuality that the individual can bring to an act is related not to their connectedness or disconnectedness to the whole but to how they themselves have been "constituted" within that whole. The "mark" of an individual on an act does not make any of their acts independent from the whole, it simply puts on the particular "color" that they've painted and been painted with. A Picasso is not a Picasso because it is disconnected from the life of his people and times and his times are not disconnected from all of time, but because all that "life" and "people" that participated in his development are put through the "sieve" of Picasso's individuality and reformulated in his art. It is not that the individual is separate from the whole but that life is reinstated, re-elaborated and re-structures anew in every individual so that "life" continues to actualize and transform itself. 


If we looked at the phenomenon from the point of view of the cells within an individual, each cell, although short lived, carries "life" for a short period of the organisms existence. It is a fact that each cell is free enough to act against the organism and develop a cancer and in that capacity resides its individualism but it is also a fact that it can support and enhance the individual's life experience. The fact that whether it develops "cancer" or "life" is not dependent on it's sole individuality but on the general state of the human being that it lives in, gives an accurate parallel of the place of the individual within society. If he or she commits suicide or wins the nobel prize does not depend solely on him or her or solely on the society that they grew up in but on both, for both are an integral aspect of each other.


It's worth realizing that the status quo of no matter what family, institution or nation does not like to assume its responsibility on failure and reducing somebody's suicide to a purely individualistic act relieves them from that responsibility. To state that the person in question was "crazy" and justify their death with that, simply "buffers" the truth: that everyone is directly and indirectly connected to that death, consciously or unconsciously responsible for it. But the same thing happens with murderers: everyone is responsible for the murderer although only the murderer committed the crime. 


It's also interesting to realize that we seem to become conscious of things as we develop and that is how it should be. We, human beings, cannot be more than we are just like an individual cannot be more than he is at a given moment in time even though the next day after an accident or some other shocking experience he or she might be a completely different being. That we become more conscious of the truth and our selves over time is simply the realization that we are in a process and that what we can know and understand today is only a glimpse of what future generations will know and understand. The Human "being" as a whole is also in its own process and the fact that one individual can understand more than the whole of humanity at a given moment in time does not mean that that individual is superior to the whole but that the whole has moved into a more conscious aspect of itself through that individual's life. All that is true only in as much as an intellectual understanding is being searched for. Consciousness is not a question of quantity. Where it rises does not mean it is disconnected just like flowers bloom in all parts of the world as an expression of life. It's very much like the colors of the rainbow: they don't exist without light.






  


Deliberate taking: the author, agency and suicide 

Katrina Jaworski 

Abstract 
In the essay, ‘What is an author?’, Michel Foucault (1984, pp. 118– 
119) contended that ‘the author does not precede the works’. If this is 
the case, then what happens when the notion of the author as never 
outside discourse is grafted to suicide? What happens when suicide – 
most commonly defined as a deliberate taking of one’s life – is read 
through the idea that the one who is doing the taking does not precede 
it? Does this not obliterate agency in suicide: the key ingredient 
necessary to marking the individual as the sole author of their death? I 
respond to these questions by first considering what Foucault’s 
contention might offer to understanding the constitution of agency in 
the act of suicide. I then draw on elements of Judith Butler’s work to 
consider a way of thinking of suicide that furthers Foucault’s 
contribution. I suggest that positioning suicide as already part of 
discourse does not undermine the individual as the author of death, or 
make the act of taking one’s life any less deliberate. I conclude with a 
comment on Foucault’s position on death being power’s limit, and 
what this might mean for understanding suicide. 



1 

Suicide is commonly understood as an explicitly individual choice and act. In this paper I will 
focus on suicide as an act that takes place in private. My aim is to render an understanding of 
the act of suicide as never outside discourse. If the act of suicide appears as outside discourse, 
it is because its intelligibility and authorship are already part of discourse. 

For explanatory purposes, a common understanding of suicide can be articulated as follows. 
The Australian Bureau of Statistics, for instance, defines suicide as ‘the deliberate taking of 
one’s life’ (2004, p. 3). In this manner, suicide is situated as an explicitly individual act where 
the individual, as the author of the act, is solely responsible for the act. At the centre of the 
act stands an individual to whom the decision to die belongs. As such, the deliberate choice 
decided by the agent appears to be determined largely by the activities of a disembodied 
mind, and the absent presence of a body which does the taking of life. The latter is not 
identified directly, even though it is the necessary site of activity. Yet suicide is an explicitly 
individual act not because a person is automatically responsible, but because they are hailed 
as being responsible. By having responsibility attributed to them, the individual is situated as 
the original source for the intention to suicide. At the same time, suicide is marked by a 
‘doing’, made apparent by the taking of life that expresses an outcome. It is unclear what the 
outcome will be, other than there must be one to signify the taking. What is made clear is that 
the intention behind the taking must be deliberate in order to have the outcome recognised as 
a suicide. 

What happens to understanding suicide as an explicitly individual choice and act, if, as 
Foucault (1984, pp. 118–119) contended, ‘the author does not precede the works’? How can 
someone be an author of their act of suicide if the one who is doing the taking does not 
precede it? Does this not obliterate agency and intention in suicide: the key ingredient 
necessary to marking the individual as the sole author of their death? My initial answer is a 
‘yes’ to all questions, not only because the individual does not come before the act, and 
thereby cannot be its author, but also because the individual, as the origin for the expression 
of the act, appears to be absent. 

My response can be substantiated by further drawing on Foucault’s position. For Foucault 
(1984), the individuality of the author is questionable. Foucault (p. 105) suggested that 
authors as individual writers – those who hold a priori status – have disappeared. Instead, 
what is left of the author is a name that serves to represent modes of being via particular 


2 

practices that ‘systematically form the objects of which they speak’ (Foucault 1972, p. 49). 
Thus, the author’s name projects the individual as a coherent source of expression to 
neutralise the normative yet contradictory workings of power relations in a way that their 
workings remain foiled (Foucault 1984, pp. 108, 113). In this sense, authors are never located 
outside discourse. If they are prediscursive, then this is only ‘if one admits that this 
prediscursive is still discursive, that is, that they do not specify a thought, or a consciousness, 
or a group of representations’ (Foucault 1972, p. 76). 

To graft Foucault’s line of thought to suicide, it would seem that the individual is less likely 
to be the sole author of their death. With this lack of authorship, it seems that the wilfulness 
to take one’s life deliberately is in doubt, since the individual as the source of expressing the 
act is suspended by something outside them. If a ‘taking’ is taking place in the act, then this 
taking does not belong to the individual and, presumably, the act of death is not theirs, nor the 
agency required to enable the deliberateness behind the act. To settle for this resolve, 
however, would be a mistake, since Foucault’s position can offer more to understanding the 
constitution of agency in the material act of suicide. To get there, I want to draw on elements 
of Butler’s work on performative and performativity, as it enables a more nuanced reading of 
suicide, through which it is possible to gain insight into the macro discursive mechanics of 
Foucault’s contribution to understanding the author and authorship. 

In her work on sex and gender, Butler (1990, p. 25) re-articulates Nietzsche’s view that there 
is no doer behind expressed deeds, as the doer and the deeds are constituted by expressions 
themselves, rather than the doer being the original source for constituting the expressions. In 
this sense, gender as performative is ‘a set of repeated acts within a highly rigid regulatory 
frame that congeal over time to produce the appearance’ of sex as the natural and original 
source of expressing gender rather than being a discursive effect like gender (Butler 1990, p. 
33). Butler builds on this position later by contending that performativity can be seen as a 
reiterative and citational practice through which discourses of sex and gender produce the 
effects they name. Gender is repeated and ritualised through actions that precede, constrain 
and exceed the doer, whether it is through particular bodily gestures, speaking or being hailed 
by bodies and actions of others (Butler 1993; 1997). The trick of power is to make the doer 
and the deed look like the deed belongs to the doer as the sole author of the deed. 



3 

Suicide can be read as performative in that it can be seen as a ‘doing’. Suicide has a 
performative representation – a set of repeated bodily acts. These produce the effect of the 
individual as being the author of taking their own life – as being deliberate in and through the 
taking. To draw heavily on Butler, suicide is constituted by the very expressions that are said 
to be its results. Across the surfaces of the suicided body suicide is produced and rendered 
visible by rituals that condition the deliberateness in the taking of one’s life. For the sake of 
clarity, I will situate these as a set of interrelated imagined ‘movie stills’, bearing in mind that 
these may or may not lead to particular outcomes. The taking of life by someone might 
consist of: a) thinking about suicide, b) imagining possible outcomes, c) writing a note, d) 
gaining access to specific means to do it, e) estimating what might be lethal, or perhaps what 
is a culturally and socially ‘appropriate’ method, f) planning the location of the act, g) 
performing the actual act, e.g. pulling the trigger or swallowing the pills, and h) awaiting the 
loss of consciousness unless it has already happened, providing no one has intervened. In 
other words, suicide materialises on the basis of these particular rituals and corporeal gestures 
that bring into existence the taking of one’s life. These gestures are bodily acts, already part 
of the activities of the mind, even if they appear disengaged from the mind. 

Yet suicide as performative does not rest with the individual alone. Whether someone lives or 
dies, different bodies of knowledge and their discursive sites of practice such as coronial 
inquest findings, medical autopsy reports and/or psychiatric assessments, become part of 
interpreting if the outcome is a suicide, and, in particular, if the individual was deliberate in 
their intentions. From another perspective, is the individual capable of taking their own life, 
without prior knowledge of something called ‘suicide’ – knowledge that in turn is shaped by 
experts, individual experiences and society at large? It is clear, for instance, that something 
other than the individual taking their life already exists. If this was not the case, then patterns 
of suicide, be it in relation to gender, age, race/ethnicity, sexuality, class, or suicide methods, 
could not be documented by the ABS (1994; 2004), or understood at a macro level. In this 
sense, suicide can be read as a reiterative and citational practice, made possible through 
norms, meanings, assumptions and knowledges identified within existing historical 
conditions and patterns, through which something about the act can be hailed and understood 
as a deliberate taking of one’s life. 

What then might we say of agency? If much of what constitutes the act resides outside the 
act, then how can the deliberate taking exist? The issue here, however, is not about 


4 

attempting to disavow the presence of agency in the act of suicide. Instead, my point is to say 
that agency has a layered history on which the deliberateness in the taking depends. What 
constitutes one’s authorship is dependent on something other than the individual without the 
act ceasing to belong to the individual’s choice to kill oneself. This is what makes the idea of 
deliberateness, and authorship, possible. One can take one’s life, and be deliberate about it, 
precisely because such a taking is shaped by repetitive conditions and prior takings, re- 
articulated when the taking occurs. Butler (2004a, p. 32) suggests that we come into the 
world on the condition that the social world is there, which means that we cannot be 
ourselves without being preceded and exceeded by something other than ourselves. To follow 
on, we cannot depart from this world, or at least try to, without something paving the way for 
the deliberate taking to take place – which for some leads to death. In this sense, it is possible 
to read suicide as relational – as never being outside discourse – without undermining the 
individual as the author of the act, or making the act of taking one’s life any less deliberate. 
In so doing, it might enable thinking about what conditions the deliberate in the taking, and 
the taking itself, who and what is part of the process of interpretation, and whose interests the 
interpretations serve. 

Foucault put forward the view that ‘death is power’s limit, the moment that escapes it’ (1978, 
p. 138). Butler disagrees with Foucault’s claim by arguing that ‘in the maintenance of death 
and of the dying, power is still at work and that death is and has its own discursive industry’ 
(1996, p. 71). In relation to suicide, death is not power’s limit, since norms, meanings and 
assumptions and the processes that are part of making sense of suicide will constitute 
knowledge of suicide before, during and after the act of taking one’s life. The fact that an 
understanding of suicide as an explicitly individual choice and act exists indicates that there 
is what can be referred to as an ‘afterlife of words’ (Butler 2005a, p. 29) – an afterlife that 
precedes and exceeds individual deaths and their authors. Dead or alive, it may not be 
possible to be free of operations of power, as a result of the effects such operations 
materialise. What might be possible, however, is that someone may no longer literally suffer 
from unbearable circumstances if they are no longer breathing. This, however, does not 
curtail the production of truths concerning their deaths, whether true or false. 

My position on understanding suicide as relational, and thereby as never outside power 
relations, raises a serious question: is it not possible to be completely free of power at least in 
death, especially if death for some becomes the means of resisting circumstances and 


5 

experiences deemed unbearable? I cannot answer this question here, other than to suggest that 
something about suicide’s intelligibility remains out of reach since the material act tends to 
take place in private. And so there may be a limit to the way power operates: a threshold 
enfolded by what is said and known of suicide and, importantly, what remains unsaid and 
silenced. To borrow from Agamben (1995; 2002), it might be useful to consider the 
possibility of a zone of indistinction, through which it is not possible to summon the exact 
truth about the act of taking one’s life, yet something of the truth about the act remains, 
caught between those who ‘have explanations for everything’, and those who ‘refuse to 
understand’, and instead generate explanations that offer so little to those who remain to 
grieve for, and remember, the dead (Agamben 2002, p. 13). Maybe then, as Foucault would 
have it, knowledge can become ‘a means of surviving by understanding’ (Foucault 1988, p. 
7). Guided by the heuristic tools offered in Foucault’s (1985; 1986), Butler’s (2000; 2004b; 
2005b) and Agamben’s (1995; 2002) works, perhaps this zone is what needs attention next to 
better understand the author, agency and suicide. 


Katrina Jaworski works as a research fellow in the Division of Health Sciences, University 
of South Australia. Her research interests include gender, bodies, death and dying, and 
suicide in particular. katrina.jaworski@unisa.edu.au 


6 

References 
Agamben, G 2002, Remnants of Auschwitz: the witness and the archive, trans. D Heller- 
Roazen, Zone Books, New York. 
Agamben, G 1995, Homo sacer: sovereign power and bare life, trans. D Heller-Roazen, 
Stanford University Press, Stanford, California. 
Australian Bureau of Statistics 2004, Suicides: recent trends, Australia 1993–2003, Cat. No. 
3309.0.55.001, Australian Government Publishing Service, Canberra. 
Australian Bureau of Statistics 1994, Suicides, Australia 1982–1992, Cat. No. 3309.0, 
Australian Government Publishing Service, Canberra. 
Butler, J 2005a, ‘On never having learned how to live’, Differences, vol. 16, no. 3, pp. 27–34. 
Butler, J 2005b, Giving an account of oneself, Fordham University Press, New York. 
Butler, J 2004a, Undoing gender, Routledge, London. 
Butler, J 2004b, Precarious life: the powers of mourning and violence, Verso, London. 
Butler, J 2000, Antigone’s claim: kinship between life and death, Columbia University Press, 
New York. 
Butler, J 1997, Excitable speech, Routledge, New York. 
Butler, J 1996, ‘Sexual subversions’, in Feminist interpretations of Michel Foucault, ed. SJ 
Hekman, Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, pp. 59–75. 
Butler, J 1993, Bodies that matter: on the discursive limits of ‘sex’, Routledge, London. 
Butler, J 1990, Gender trouble: feminism and the subversion of identity, Routledge, London. 
Foucault, M 1997 [1972], The archaeology of knowledge, trans. AM Sheridan Smith, 
Routledge, London. 
Foucault, M 1988, ‘The minimalist self’, in Politics, philosophy, culture: interviews and 
other writings 1977–1984, ed. LD Kritzman, Routledge, New York. 
Foucault, M 1986, The history of sexuality, vol. 3, trans. R Hurley, Penguin Books, London. 
Foucault, M 1985, The history of sexuality, vol. 2, trans. R Hurley, Penguin Books, London. 
Foucault, M 1984, ‘What is an author?’, in The Foucault reader: an introduction to 
Foucault’s thought, ed. P Rabinow, Penguin Books, London, pp. 101–120. 


7 

Foucault, M 1978, The history of sexuality, vol. 1, trans. R Hurley, Penguin Books, London.