ISSN: 1832-5203
Foucault Studies, No 7, pp. 18-44, September 2009
Linda Williams
Chloë Taylor, University of Alberta
passing that prostitution and pornography, like the sexual sciences of medicine and
psychiatry, are involved in the proliferation of sexualities and the perverse
implantation. Against an influential misinterpretation of this passage on the part of
film studies scholar Linda Williams, this paper takes up Foucault’s claim and
attempts to explain the mechanism through which the sex industry, and
pornography in particular, functions analogously to the sexual sciences in terms of
the normalizing form of power that Foucault describes. Whereas Williams sets the
question of prostitution aside, and argues that pornography must be a confessional
discourse for Foucault, this paper argues that consumption rather than confession is
the mechanism through which both prostitution and pornography deploy sexualities
within a disciplinary system of power.
to see the laws concerning sexual crimes reformed in France. In his response he
made no mention of prostitution and stated briefly that he was opposed to all
legislation restricting sexually explicit materials. Prostitution and pornography
appear to have been easy cases for Foucault, while he went on to say that there were
only two kinds of sex acts that troubled him with respect to legislation – rape and
sex with minors – and it is these issues that he contemplated in some detail.1 Lest we
Foucault describes this phone call in ‚Confinement, Psychiatry, Prison,‛ where he goes
on to discuss rape with his interlocutors. Soon after, in ‚Sexual Morality and the Law,‛
he addresses the issue of sex with minors. See Lawrence D. Kritzman (ed.), Michel
Foucault: Politics, Philosophy, Culture: Interviews and Other Writings, 1977-1984 (New York
and London: Routledge: 1988) 178-210 and 271-285. For critical responses to Foucault’s
comments on rape and sex with children, see Linda Alcoff, ‚Dangerous Pleasures:
Foucault and the Politics of Pedophilia,‛ in Susan J. Hekman (ed.), Feminist Interpretations
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
19
of Sexuality prostitution and pornography are mentioned along with the disciplinary
professions of medicine and psychiatry as having ‚tapped into both this analytic
multiplication of pleasure and this optimization of the power that controls it.‛2
Prostitution and pornography are suggested by Foucault to be involved in the
workings of disciplinary power as it constructs and controls sexuality, and in this
sense would be problematic indeed, even if it would make no more sense to resort to
legislation in the cases of pornography and prostitution than it would in the cases of
other disciplinary practices such as psychoanalysis and psychiatry. Since law
functions on a model of repressive, sovereign or juridical power, it is not very
effective, and may even be counter-productive, to resort to law in order to resist
what are in fact disciplinary phenomena.
Film Studies scholar Linda Williams’ highly influential study of pornography, Hard
Core: Power, Pleasure, and the ‘Frenzy of the Visible’, which draws on Foucault at length.
Williams’ 1989 work was groundbreaking in that it was the first study of porno-
graphy that declined to engage in the censorship debate. Rather than questioning
whether we should be for or against pornography, Williams approaches porno-
graphy like any other film genre, discussing it seriously in terms of influences and
techniques. Williams considers pornography to be a ‚body genre‛ of film much like
other low-brow genres such as melodrama and horror, which also work to elicit
physiological responses in the viewer. Importantly for the current paper, it is one of
Williams’ central theses in her book to take up Foucault’s association of
pornography with the disciplinary sciences of medicine and psychiatry in order to
argue that pornography is a confessional science and participates in the will to know
about sex. Moreover, Williams understands Foucault’s situating of pornography
within his discussion of the perverse implantation to mean that pornography results
in a positive proliferation of fluid sexualities within individual lives. Williams’ use
of Foucault has gone unquestioned in Film and Porn Studies and has been cited and
1996), 99-135; Vikki Bell, Interrogating Incest: Feminism, Foucault and the Law (London and
New York: Routledge, 1993); Ann J. Cahill, ‚Foucault, Rape, and the Construction of the
Feminine Body,‛ Hypatia, 15, vol., no. 1, (Winter 2000); Ann J. Cahill, Rethinking Rape
(Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 2001); Laura Hengehold, ‚An Immodest
Proposal: Foucault, Hysterization, and the ‘Second Rape,’‛ in Hypatia, (Summer 1994): 88-
107; Monique Plaza, ‚Our Damages and Their Compensation,‛ Feminist Issues, 1 (3),
([1978], 1981): 5-35; Chloë Taylor, ‚Foucault, Feminism and Sex Crimes,‛ in Hypatia, vol.
24, no. 4, (Fall 2009); Winifred Woodhull, ‚Sexuality, Power, and the Question of Rape,‛
in Irene Diamond and Lee Quinby (ed.), Feminism and Foucault: Reflections on Resistance,
(Boston: Northeastern University Press, 1988), 167-176.
2
Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality: An Introduction (New York: Vintage, 1978), 48.
Foucault Studies, No. 7, pp. 18-44
20
employed authoritatively by numerous other scholars; however, I shall contest both
Williams’ reading of Foucault and of pornography.
of Foucault’s reference to pornography (and, to a lesser extent, prostitution – which
Williams sets aside) in The History of Sexuality. This interpretation is more consistent
than Williams’ not only with Foucault’s arguments in The History of Sexuality, but
more importantly, with the manner in which pornography and prostitution actually
function. First, I argue that in so far as pornography and prostitution involve
expertise, they are closer to the ars erotica than to the sexual sciences. Second, I argue
that the mechanism by which pornography and prostitution participate in the
perverse implantation is not confession but consumption. Consequently, contra
Williams, we must attend to the consumers rather than to what takes place on set or
on screen to see how pornography serves its disciplinary function. Finally, I argue
that although the perverse implantation deployed by pornography may result in a
proliferation of sexualities at a society-wide level, on an individual level it is
constraining rather than liberating, contributing – along with the sexual sciences of
medicine and psychiatry – to the fixing of each of us into frozen rather than fluid
sexual identities.
Other than his references to specific literary works such as My Secret Life and the
writings of Sade, Foucault only considers pornography once in the History of
Sexuality, and what he says is all-too-brief and has been influentially misinterpreted
by Williams. In the chapter entitled ‚The Perverse Implantation,‛ Foucault writes:
became stuck to an age, a place, a type of practice. A proliferation of sexualities
through the extension of power; an optimization of the power to which each of
these local sexualities gave a surface of intervention; this concatenation,
particularly since the nineteenth century, has been ensured and relayed by the
countless economic interests which, with the help of medicine, psychiatry,
prostitution, and pornography, have tapped into both this analytic multiplication of
pleasure and this optimization of the power that controls it. Pleasure and power
do not cancel or turn back against one another; they seek out, overlap, and
reinforce one another. They are linked together by complex mechanisms and
devices of excitation and incitement.3
Foucault’s opposition to any censorship of sexually explicit materials. Foucault’s
main objective in this reference to prostitution and pornography is not so much to
Ibid., 48 (my italics).
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
21
in order to control it more generally, whether this repression occurs through
legislation or medicine. According to Foucault’s theory of disciplinary power as
productive, the workings of power and the very idea of repression are constitutive
rather than extinguishers of desire.4 As Foucault argues throughout the first volume
of the History of Sexuality, when we try to control desire by repressing it we in fact
produce it, and, as this passage makes clear, Foucault thinks that this is just as true
with respect to the sex industry as to the medical treatment of perversions.
relation between the sex industry and the sexual sciences, it is curious that he would
string together the apparently incongruous bedmates of medicine and psychiatry
with prostitution and pornography. Each of these practices is suggested to be
working towards similar ends within a disciplinary system of power: Foucault
suggests that pornography and prostitution, like the sexual sciences, are involved in
a ‚proliferation of sexualities,‛ which proliferation, for Foucault, is in turn caught up
with ‚the perverse implantation,‛ as the chapter in which this citation occurs
explains. Unfortunately, whereas in the case of medicine and psychiatry Foucault
describes the precise mechanism through which this proliferation and implantation
of sexualities occurs – confession – he does not give us a similar account of the
manners in which prostitution and pornography deploy sexualities. In response to
this passage, Williams has deduced that pornography simply is a sexual science for
Foucault, and thus employs the same technology of deployment as the ‚other‛ sexual
sciences. Setting the issue of prostitution aside – and even replacing the word
‚prostitution‛ with ‚law‛ in her reference to this passage5 – Williams has argued that
pornography is a confessional practice. As I shall argue below, however, and as is
suggested by Williams’ own need to switch the word ‚prostitution‛ for the more
obviously confessional practice of ‚law‛ in her manipulation of Foucault’s phrase,
this is far from clear. In fact, to make sense of this citation, we need to understand
how both pornography and prostitution function to deploy sexualities in a manner
that is analogous (but not necessarily identical) to the workings of the sexual
sciences.
the disentanglement of sex from truth and identity. He famously concludes this
work by proposing that ‚The rallying point for the counterattack against the
deployment of sexuality ought not to be sex-desire, but bodies and pleasures.‛6
Ibid., 158.
5
Linda Williams, Hard Core: Power, Pleasure, and the ‚Frenzy of the Visible‛ (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press, 1989), 35.
6
Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 157.
Foucault Studies, No. 7, pp. 18-44
22
Rather than trying to find out what we already or truly are through introspections
into our sex(uality) and desires, we should work on what we might become, what
new pleasures and capacities of the body we might discover. In this initial volume,
Foucault explores the possibility of mastering the body and its pleasures in terms of
the Eastern ars erotica.7 A few years later, he would describe this discussion of the ars
erotica as ‚one of the numerous points where I was wrong in that book,‛ not because
what he said there was false, but because he ‚should have opposed our science of
sex to a contrasting practice in our own culture. The Greeks and Romans did not
have any ars erotica to be compared with the Chinese ars erotica *<+ They had a
techne tou biou [care of the self] in which the economy of pleasure played a very large
role.‛8 Foucault now contrasts the sexual sciences not to Eastern erotic arts, but to
Greek and Roman practices of self-care, and provides a schematic account of the
different approaches to sexuality in each of these cultures – the East, the ancient
West, and the Christian and modern West:
– we have the Greek ‚formula‛ *<+ In this Greek formula what is underscored
is ‚act,‛ with pleasure and desire as subsidiary: acte – plaisir – (désir). *<+
because you have to restrain acts in order to get the maximum duration and
intensity of pleasure.
have to become something neutral; you have to act only to produce children, or
to fulfill your conjugal duty. And pleasure is both practically and theoretically
excluded: (désir) – acte – (plaisir). Desire is practically excluded – you have to
eradicate your desire – but theoretically very important.
underlined and practically accepted, since you have to liberate your own desire.
Acts are not very important, and pleasure – nobody knows what it is!9
techniques of mastering the pleasure-capacities of the body to be an area of
knowledge external to the self that a subject can acquire through corporeal practice
under the tutelage of a master. Ancient practices of self-care were concerned with an
Ibid., 57-71.
8
Michel Foucault, ‚On the Genealogy of Ethics,‛ in Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow,
Michel Foucault, Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Press, 1993), 234-235.
9
Ibid., 242-243.
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
23
interest in desire. As Foucault writes:
him, his behavior was valued. The problem was, does he touch the boy or not.
That’s the ethical substance: the act linked with pleasure and desire. For
Augustine it’s very clear that when he remembers his relationship to his young
friend when he was eighteen years old, what bothers him is what exactly was the
kind of desire he had for him. So, you see that the ethical substance has
changed.10
emphasis from acts to desires, is still with us today. While desire remains the aspect
of sex which we stress, it has now become positive rather than negative: whereas
Augustine worried about the nature of his desire in order to better annihilate it, we
now seek to identify our desires in order to affirm and inhabit our authentic
sexualities, and we take desire, rather than acts or pleasures, to be the key to
unlocking the secrets of our souls.
succeeded in eclipsing sexual acts almost entirely. With the scientia sexualis there is
no need to act at all in order to have and to discover our sexualities, we just need to
think about our personal desires and the types of selves that these constitute. For
the scientia sexualis, sexual truth is already in the psyche, if we only introspect on our
feelings, fantasies, dreams, childhood traumas, repressions and inhibitions. Sexual
truth is psychologized, or is specific to each individual and need not be acted upon,
in contrast to the ars erotica, for which the truths of sexual pleasure are mysteries into
which one must be initiated, which must be practiced, and which have nothing to do
with the individual practitioner or her psychic states.
scientia sexualis, these are scientists who may or may not have much sexual
experience or much embodied knowledge of pleasure but who are medically-trained
decipherers of desire, interpreters of sexual confessions, taxonomers of perversions
or psychosexual types. The sexual experts of the ars erotica, on the other hand, are
trained in the mastery of non-individuated bodies and pleasures.11 Studying the ars
Ibid., 238.
11
Bodies may be individuated in the ars erotica into a few physiological types: for instance,
in the Kama Sutra, male bodies come in hare, bull, and horse types, and women come in
deer, mare, and elephant types, according to the size of their genitals. Bodies also come
with different degrees of passion – deemed small, middling, or extreme – and the Kama
Sutra urges lovers to find partners who correspond to themselves in genital size and force
Foucault Studies, No. 7, pp. 18-44
24
erotica would consequently be a deindividualizing practice. Unlike patients and
practitioners of the scientia sexualis, an initiate of the ars erotica would not be
concerned with understanding her own individual sexuality, or the various
individual sexualities (perversions, etc.) of others, but in understanding the
pleasures of bodies per se. While corporeal pleasure is important to the ars erotica,
the Western obsession with sexual identity has no more place in these Eastern
practices than it did in the self-mastering techniques of the ancient Greeks.
Foucault discusses in the History of Sexuality. Williams’ initial argument for the
pornography/sexual science identification involves showing that pornography and
two modern scientific developments – photography and psychoanalysis – came of
age together, and share a history that has not been disentangled since. As Williams
documents, the scientific inventions of photography were quickly employed to
produce pornography, while sexual scientists such as Charcot took quasi-
pornographic photographs with titles such as ‚Ècstase.‛ Science, psychiatry,
psychoanalysis, and pornography thus have an interactive history, and this history
is one of the grounds for Williams’ blurring of the notions of pornography and
sexual science. The use and making of pornographic images in the history of the
sciences of psychiatry and psychoanalysis is not enough to establish pornography as
a sexual science, however, or even to say that it is like a science. Charcot touched
many things, and early scientist-photographers worked in many genres, but not all
of these became science.
of pornography are situated in the particularly modern and Western ‚will to know‛
about sex, which volonté de savoir is also what motivates the sexual sciences.
Foucault’s argument is that we, as a society, want to know about sex, since we have
come to think that sex is the key to understanding who we are, the means to
realizing both our truth and our happiness. It is in this context that we participate in
the studies of the sexual sciences, undergo analysis and self-analysis, and consume
the books, magazines, and television shows that feature sexological knowledge. In
this context, pornography is interpreted by Williams – and by authors who cite
Williams’ study such as Chris Straayer, Julie Lavigne and Gertrud Koch – as catering
to this same will to know the truth about sex. Like sexual scientists in their
interrogations, Williams thinks that we consume pornography out of the desire to
hear ‚sex speak‛ or to witness sexual confessions.
less individualizing than, the psychosexual taxonomies of the sexual sciences.
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
25
pornographic images, Koch shows a reverse movement, pointing to cases in which
pornographers made overtures to the sexual sciences. She points out that certain
pornographic films ‛declared their intention to offer practical advice for living, to be
purveyors of knowledge. Examples of these are the Oswald Kolle series, or Helga.
The classification of formal knowledge by category still attaches to an unending
series of ‘Film Reports,’ often presenting sexual behaviour according to various
occupations.‛12 Koch goes on to note that certain ‚early porn films displayed a
lexicographic tendency,‛ and quotes two descriptions from a 1956 essay by Curt
Moreck:
presentation of every imaginable perversion. Although life itself very often
offers the connoisseur a view of simple vice, the chance to enjoy real perversity
as a spectator is much rarer; in this case, film tries to fill the void. There are some
films in this genre which seem to have been staged directly from Krafft-Ebing’s
Psychopathia Sexualis, as a manual of abnormal sexual operations for civilized
man.
fifty ways from the old Treatise on the Hundred and Fifty Ways of Loving was
demonstrated, with occasional interruptions for lesbian, pederast, and
masturbation jokes. All that was harmless. Sadists and masochists waved their
instruments, sodomy was practiced, coprophagous acts were on display.13
sort of material which the sexual sciences study. Indeed, Krafft-Ebing used the
pornographic texts of Sade and Sacher-Masoch to identify the characteristics of
sadism and masochism. Some pornographic films could function like the texts of
Sade and Sacher-Masoch as other illustrations of perversions which the sexual
scientists might analyze. As Foucault notes, the anonymous author of My Secret Life
described the value of his writings as a quasi-scientific contribution to human
knowledge of sexuality.14 In instances such as these – voluntarily in the cases of My
Secret Life and the films that Moreck describes, and involuntarily in the cases of Sade
and Sacher-Masoch – pornography serves as material for the sexual scientists’
studies of perversion. In the case of My Secret Life, because it is the author himself
who offers his experiences to the scientists, and because the text is written in an
autobiographical mode, pornography works as the kind of confession which sexual
scientists elicit from their patients. In the other cases, the data is more dubious and
Gertrud Koch, ‚The Body’s Shadow Realm,‛ in Pamela Church Gibson (ed.), More Dirty
Looks: Gender, Pornography and Power (London: The British Film Institute, 2004), 155.
13
Cited in Koch, 155.
14
Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 22.
Foucault Studies, No. 7, pp. 18-44
26
involuntarily provided, and Sacher-Masoch was appalled to find a sexual perversion
named after himself in the Psychopathia Sexualis on the basis of his literary works.
work by claiming to contribute to scientific knowledge, and a few have done so in an
autobiographical or confessional mode, it is surely the case that most pornography is
not autobiographical and is not offered up as quasi-scientific information about
human sexuality, but as fiction and fantasy. Significantly, while anti-pornography
feminists have regularly claimed that pornography reflects and reinscribes (a
misogynist) reality, the pornography industry and its defenders persistently argue
that their opponents are failing to distinguish between fantasy and reality.
Pornography, they argue, is not truth but fantasy, and the people who consume it
realize this. The value of pornography to society is defended as art and imagination,
and not as science, knowledge, or truth.
it shows that some works of pornography have engaged with and even hoped to
contribute to or collaborate with the sexual sciences, this is not a feature of most
pornography, either in the nineteenth century or today. It is in fact highly
questionable whether pornography arises primarily out of a ‚will to know‛ about
sex at all. For one thing, mass-produced and circulated pornography pre-existed the
volonté de savoir that Foucault describes. While Williams begins her study of the
history of pornography with the invention of photography in the nineteenth century,
thus making it contemporary with Charcot, she might have begun with the
invention of the printing press in the fifteenth century instead. Like the invention of
the camera, the invention of the printing press quickly gave rise to the mass
production and circulation of pornographic works, such as Guilio Romano’s 1520
series, I modi, and this well before the age of the ‚will to know‛ about sex that
Foucault describes.15 It is thus quite possible for a society to make, distribute, and
consume pornography on a large scale with non-epistemological motivations and
prior to the existence of the sexual sciences, and this leads me to doubt that the
primary impulse behind the production and consumption of pornography is any
more part of a volonté de savoir today than it was in the 1520s.
Renaissance, and yet even in this age of the will to know about sex, it is far from
clear that it is in the spirit of knowledge that pornography is either made or
consumed. Do people consume pornography to learn about sexual pleasure or to
Bette Talvacchia, Taking Positions: On the Erotic in Renaissance Culture (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1999)
27
graphy an epistemological endeavor or a masturbatory aid? Are these necessarily
inter-related? Epistemological pursuits may certainly be prurient, and Foucault
himself characterizes fin-de-siècle medicine as ‚a pornography of the morbid,‛16 but
does all sexual pleasure today seek the truth of sex? Williams seems to think that it
does, for she even includes peep shows under the umbrella of the ‚scientific will-to-
knowledge.‛17
and that it can play an educative role, for better or for worse, but I am not sure that
this educative role is the primary motivation or function of pornography, its
explanation or raison d’être. According to one poll, eight-six percent of respondants
think that pornography is educational, and Pamela Paul writes that young men in
particular may use pornography ‚to figure out what women want and expect from
sex. In fact, studies show that men learn from and emulate what they see in
pornography.‛18 I shall argue below that mainstream heterosexual pornography
does not so much educate men in women’s desires as construct a fantasy for men
according to which women’s desires and pleasures correspond to their own.
Something similar might be said about prostitution, which is also often used for
male sexual initiation and education, but which in fact probably teaches men very
little about women’s actual pleasures or desires. Here, however, I want to argue that
in so far as advocates say that pornography (or prostitution) is educational, they
mean that it teaches sexual skills or techniques, not truths about the psychosexualities
and desires of the individuals on-screen or employed. This, for Foucault, would
situate pornography (and prostitution) closer to the ars erotica than the scientia
sexualis. To recall, the sexual experts of the ars erotica are trained in practices that
bring about pleasure and have mastered an art of manipulating bodies, while the
sexual experts of the scientia sexualis are trained in diagnosing psychological
perversions and interpreting desires. If porn stars (and prostitutes) are ‚sexual
experts‛ of a sort, capable of contributing to the sexual education of consumers, it is
in the manner of the ars erotica and not of the sexual sciences.
frequently claimed. It is nevertheless not clear that this situates pornography on the
side of the sexual sciences, and moreover it is not clear that this is very often the
main purpose in consuming pornography, or that it is a consumer’s primary
Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 54.
17
Williams, 51.
18
Pamela Paul, Pornified: How Pornography is Damaging Our Lives, Our Relationships, and Our
Families (New York: Times Books, 2005), 18.
28
motivation or merely a side-effect. Since pornography tends to be repetitious, it also
seems unlikely that viewers continue to watch pornography for its educational
function. After a short time, one has likely learned what pornography has to teach,
but many go on watching pornography for other reasons, which reasons were
probably the main motivation in the first place.
pornography arises and is consumed out of a will to know about sex, it is important
to note that not everything that engages in this volonté de savoir becomes a sexual
science. Foucault himself observes that the desire to confess and to hear confessed
the truths of sex quickly expanded beyond the scientific realm, and finds expression
today in our intimate conversations with family members, friends, and lovers and in
‚‘scandalous’ literature.‛19 Indeed, the confessional impulse does not merely
characterize our speaking about sex, for Foucault, but modern subjectivity more
generally, or the wide-spread trend toward psychologization. For instance, Foucault
discuss the manners in which criminal law became psychiatrized and involves
confessional practices in the modern era, even in cases which have nothing to do
with sexuality.20 For Foucault, this does not transform law, ‚scandalous literature,‛
or pillow talk into science, although it indicates that they interact with the human
sciences in interesting and problematic ways.
Williams, however, argues that pornography in general (and not only in a few
autobiographical instances) is a sexual science, and that it functions in our society as
the sort of confession which the sexual sciences elicit and which Foucault examined.
According to Williams, pornography is consumed as a confessional genre, and as a
confessional source of truthful information about female pleasure in particular. She
writes that pornography has ‚the goal of making visible the involuntary confession
of bodily pleasure.‛21 In this way ‚We begin to see *<+ how this sexual science gives
form to the ‘truths’ that are confessed.‛22 In particular, ‚Hard core desires assurance
that it is witnessing not the voluntary performance of feminine pleasure, but its
involuntary confession.‛23 Pornography, according to Williams, is not just
Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 21.
20
Michel Foucault, ‚Confinement, Psychiatry, Prison,‛ and ‚The Dangerous Individual,‛ in
Lawrence D. Kritzman (ed.), Michel Foucault: Politics, Philosophy, Culture: Interviews and
Other Writings, 1977-1984 (New York and London: Routledge, 1988), 178-210 and 125-151.
21
Williams, 50.
22
Ibid., 48.
23
Ibid.,, 50.
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
29
confessions of the hidden secrets of female pleasure.‛25
‚confessions‛ from porn stars, obscures the point, the more sophisticated version of
Williams’ argument is not that the porn stars are actually confessing, but that
pornography aims to produce the illusion of confession, and that pornographic films
are consumed as confessions. Referring to Diderot’s tale of the speaking sex, as
discussed by Foucault, Williams writes that ‚Motion pictures *pornography+ take
over from the magic of Mongogul’s silver ring to offer the illusion of a more truthful,
hard-core confession.‛26 Williams thus realizes that it is in fact male directors
catering to male viewers who have been doing most of the ‚speaking‛ in
pornography, so that if male viewers think that they are ‚hearing‛ confessions of
female pleasure ‚spoken‛ through close-ups of female genitals engaged in real sex,
this involves mostly male pornographers ventriloquizing their voices into the vulvas
of their female stars. However, Williams asserts that this is equally true of the
‚other‛ sexual sciences:
‘lacking’ that cinema participates in as well. Neither institution actually reflects
the confessional truths they purport to record; rather, they produce these truths
in their new forms of power and pleasure.27
their female patients any more than the pornographers do, and yet what they said,
like the images that the pornographers produce, is productive of truth. Doctors and
pornographers, according to Williams, both give us confessions of female pleasure
as seen through the lens of male interpretation and desire in manners that do not so
much reflect as construct the truth of female sexuality. In one example, Williams
describes staged photographs of a faked hysterical attack by the photographer
Muybridge as other ‚‘confessions’ of a female body.‛28 Even pornographic literature
written by male writers is interpreted by Williams as ‚confessions‛ of female
pleasure:
often focused on women) of female pleasure *<+ and the more direct and
graphic confession of pleasure by women’s bodies in hard core. Both are
Ibid., 122.
25
Ibid., 53.
26
Ibid., 32.
27
Ibid., 46.
28
Ibid., 47-48.
Foucault Studies, No. 7, pp. 18-44
30
examples of men speaking about women’s sex to other men; both want to know
more about the pleasures of women *<+.29
of female pleasure, then so can pornography be – but does anyone read Fanny Hill
this way?
hysterical fit for Muybridge, or the ‚hysterics‛ who performed for Charcot, are thus
not really confessing, for Williams, but she claims that they are viewed as confessing,
especially during their ‚involuntary convulsions‛ or orgasms, authentic or
otherwise, and that their performances function as confessions in the production of
knowledge about sex. According to Williams, it is because we watch pornography
to see confessions that the orgasm must be as visible as possible, as evidenced by the
de rigueur ‚money shot‛ in the case of male porn stars. For Williams, it is a major
problem for the pornography industry that women do not (usually) produce
similarly visible ‚confessions,‛ when ‚involuntary confessions of pleasure‛ –
especially female pleasure – is what hard core is all about.
clear why Williams consistently associates pornographic orgasms with
involuntariness. In the case of ‚money shots,‛ which Williams repeatedly calls
‚involuntary confessions of pleasure,‛ Williams herself tells us that male porn stars
are paid extra for these scenes, and thus certainly intend them. It is also not clear
that confessions in general should be characterized as ‚involuntary.‛ While Foucault
stresses that confessions are authenticated by the inhibitions that they overcome, this
does not make them involuntary but rather feats of voluntary effort. In a legal
context, an involuntary statement does not qualify as a confession at all. In
literature, texts written in the third person and texts in which the first person
narrator’s name does not correspond with the author’s name (for instance, Fanny
Hill does not correspond with John Cleland) are also not considered confessional.30
In The History of Sexuality, Foucault describes confession as ‚a ritual of discourse
where the subject who speaks corresponds with the subject of the statement,‛31
which cannot be said for any of the cases which Williams is calling ‚confession.‛
statement made by one person to another about herself, whether this statement
Ibid., 55-56.
30
Philippe Lejeune, ‚Le pacte autobiographique,‛ in Philippe Lejeune, Le pacte Autobio-
graphique (Paris: Seuil, 1975), 13-46.
31
Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 61.
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
31
make about ourselves is considered to be a confession, however: calling a statement
a confession implies that it speaks of something that is shameful, difficult to say, or
revelatory of who the speaker is. According to Foucault, confession is a discursive
act that individuates us, and it is one of the privileged forms of truth-telling and self-
constitution in our culture. In ‚Subjectivity and Truth‛ Foucault defines confession
as: ‚To declare aloud and intelligibly the truth of oneself.‛32 In The History of
Sexuality, confession is ‚a ritual which unfolds in a relation of power, since one
doesn’t confess without the presence, at least the virtual presence, of a partner who
is not simply an interlocutor but the agency that requires the confession, imposes it,
weighs it, and intervenes to judge, punish, pardon, console, reconcile.‛33 For
Foucault, confession is also ‚a ritual where truth is authenticated by the obstacles
and resistances that it has had to lift in order to be formulated,‛ or one that is always
told with difficulty and shame. Finally, it is a discursive act in which ‚articulation
alone, independently of its external consequences, produces, in the person who
articulates it, intrinsic modifications: it makes him innocent, it redeems him, purifies
him, promises him salvation.‛34 In a later essay, ‚Christianity and Confession,‛
Foucault furthermore makes clear that confession must be verbal and not merely
performative. To make this point, he recounts a story from Cassian in which a monk
who stole a loaf of bread each day experiences repentance during a sermon, and
therefore performatively reveals to those congregated the loaf of bread hidden under
his robes, and then confesses verbally to having stolen and eaten a loaf each day.
Only when he makes a verbal confession does ‚a light *seem+ to tear itself away
from his body and cross the room, spreading a disgusting smell of sulphur.‛35 Satan
and his temptations were not dislodged from the monk at the moment that he felt
contrition, nor at the moment that he displayed the stolen loaf to his fellows and
thus theatrically exposed his guilt. Only when he confessed his wrongdoing in
words was the Devil forced from his body. Foucault uses this story to argue that
confession is discursive rather than performative, unlike earlier, pre-confessional
forms of Christian penance.
telling, confession is interpersonal, discursive, autobiographical, difficult or
shameful, and subject-forming. This said, can pornography be described as
Michel Foucault, ‚Subjectivity and Truth,‛ in The Politics of Truth. Los Angeles, CA:
Semiotext(e), (1997), 173.
33
Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 61.
34
Ibid., 62.
35
Michel Foucault, ‚Christianity and Confession,‛ in The Politics of Truth. Los Angeles, CA:
Semiotext(e), (1997), 222-223.
32
confessional according to Foucault’s analysis of confession? Contra Williams, I
would argue that it cannot for the following reasons. First, the relation between
actors and viewers in pornography is not an interpersonal one, and the acts involved
are theatrical performances rather than discursive acts. Moreover, although this
point requires more explanation, it does not seem to me that the actors are
overcoming inhibitions in order to confess/perform pleasures which are subject-
forming, constitutive of their identities, or individuating. Performing in a
pornographic film, like engaging in prostitution, may be taken as constitutive of
psychosexual subjectivity in the modern West in that it is assumed to damage the
sex worker’s authentic sexuality.36 In this case, however, her authentic sexuality is
not what gets performed in either the brothel or the set, but is what gets obscured in
this process. According to this negative view of pornography, what we see in a
pornographic film is not an expression of the porn star’s sexuality, but a possibly
permanent and damaging obscuration of it.
in the eyes of viewers and for the stars themselves is insofar as such performances
constitute her according to the identity of ‚sex worker‛ or ‚whore,‛ regardless of the
nature of the particular sex acts in which she is engaged; in other words, performing
as a dominatrix in a pornographic film does not constitute the actress as a
dominatrix in her own eyes or those of her viewers, but it may constitute her as a sex
worker or a whore, with all the stigmatization that this entails in a society such as
ours. Men interviewed in Pornified note that they would not date or marry the
actresses who arouse them, precisely because of the type of woman that performing
in pornographic films makes them. Performing in pornographic films functions to
constitute actors as porn stars/whores for their viewers and probably for themselves,
whatever (possibly more positive) meaning this has for them, but it does not
constitute them as, say, lesbians if they engage in lesbian sex scenes, or
sadomasochists if they perform in s/m scenes, for the precise reason that they engage
in these acts as theatrical performances and they are consumed as such. Williams is not
arguing that the porn stars are seen as confessing to being porn stars, however, but
that they are seen as confessing to pleasure, to truths about female sexuality, or to
their own feminine pleasure in particular acts, which does not seem to be the case.
films to be confessions for the very simple reason that they are fictional and not
autobiographies or documentaries. Pornography does not declare itself to be a
truth-telling genre, but fantasy catering to the desires of its viewers (not its actors),
This view is widespread, but see, for instance, Igor Primoratz, ‚What’s Wrong with
Prostitution?‛ in Alan Soble (ed.), The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings (Lanham,
Boulder, CO, New York and Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2002), 455.
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
33
quasi-legalistic and particularly authentic cases of truth-telling or self-revelation.37
Peter Brooks, in his study of confession, notes that ‚Western literature has made the
confessional mode a crucial kind of self-expression that is supposed to bear a special
stamp of sincerity and authenticity and to bear special witness to the truth of the
individual personality.‛38 We do not consider a pornographic sex scene to be
particularly sincere, or to be any more confessional than a Hollywood sex scene,
even though, unlike in Hollywood films, porn stars are having real sex, as
demonstrated by the all important ‚meat shots‛ and ‚money shots‛ that characterize
hard-core. Although the act or sex is real, it is not true: porn stars are not telling the
truth of their sex or their desire. We see acts and maybe pleasures in porn, but we do
not know (and, as I shall argue below, I do not think that we care) if we are seeing
desire. In this sense, again, pornography seems closer to the ars erotica than to the
scientia sexualis.
sex and the truth of an individual’s sexuality, and between acts and pleasure on the one
hand, and sexuality and desire on the other. For Foucault, however, these are crucial
distinctions, indicative of the epistemic transition to modernity, or the shift in
importance from act to actor, deed to desire.39 An individual may be considered a
pedophile even if he has never acted on his desires, but only demonstrated them
through certain fantasies, consuming certain literature or websites, just as a person
may consider herself to be bisexual even if she has only had heterosexual sex, on the
basis of her longings. We evidently think that the sexual acts we perform in reality
may have little to do with the truth of our sex. For this reason, as Foucault makes
clear in The History of Sexuality, sexual confessions (and even legal or criminal
confessions) may or may not be about what a person really does, but they are always
Lejeune, 13-46.
38
Peter Brooks, Troubling Confessions: Speaking Guilt in Law and Literature (Chicago, IL:
Chicago University Press, 2000), 18.
39
Foucault stresses this shift towards psychologization in many contexts. As seen above,
he contrasts the Eastern interest in bodies and pleasures to the Western focus on
sexuality and desire. In later works, Foucault contrasted ancient Greek and Roman
practices of self-mastery focusing on acts to the modern fixation on desires. For Foucault,
it is a peculiarity of the modern West that truth does not lie in what we have done but in
what we feel. Foucault notes a similar manifestation of this shift in interest from deed to
desire, act to actor, with respect to law: while in the past judges were only concerned
with crimes – or with establishing what had happened, who did it, and what punishment
corresponded – today they are at least as concerned with criminals, or with the psyches,
motivations, intentions, childhood histories, regrets, and likelihood of recidivism.
Foucault makes this point frequently, for instance in ‚Confinement, Psychiatry, Prison,‛
‚The Dangerous Individual,‛ and Discipline and Punish, among other places.
Foucault Studies, No. 7, pp. 18-44
34
and more importantly concerned with what he or she wants to do. This is why
confessions are importantly discursive rather than theatrical. While Williams thinks
that pornography is confessional precisely because it uses bright lights and close-up
camera shots, or is a ‚frenzy of the visible,‛ confessions are in fact about the
invisible, what cannot be seen and must therefore be said – or whispered. Contra
Williams, the invisibility of the female orgasm in fact poses no problem at all for a
confessional discourse, even if it poses a problem for pornography.
the male actors are having real orgasms or some degree of real pleasure, even if they
need to take Viagra to achieve it. However, we have no idea how they feel about it,
what their intentions and motivations are, what histories led up to their being where
they are, or if either the male or the female actors are expressing the truth of their
desires. What Williams does not see in her repeated references to these so-called
‚involuntary confessions of pleasure‛ is that, confessionally-speaking, pleasure is
not nearly as important as desire, and meat shots and money shots do not tell us
about desire – or, in a point to which I shall return below, at least not about the
desires of the actors.
pornography are concerned about the authenticity (or truthfulness) of the actor’s
pleasures and desires, and this again indicates that they do not consume porn as a
confessional genre or out of a ‚will to know‛ about the sex(uality) of those on-
screen. One indication of this is that although there is a widespread belief that many
actresses in pornographic films are sexually exploited and abused, this does not
seem to change the experience of viewers, indicating that they are not interested in
what the porn star’s true desires, pleasures, or psychic states are, as long as she
performs well and the sex is real.40
In At Home with Pornography: Women, Sex, and Everyday Life (New York: New York Uni-
versity Press, 1998), Jane Juffer discusses the case of one porn film in which the porn stars
are supposedly performing their own desires. The marketing gimmick for this work is
that it is allegedly undirected, and so provides viewers with a rare opportunity to see
porn stars expressing their true sexualities and pursuing their actual fantasies. Juffer
writes:
stars perform a vast number of sex acts in what is billed as an expression of
their authentic and outrageous sexualities. Says producer Henri Pachard
before the MTV-style video begins, ‘You’re going to see something
different – exhibitionists given the freedom to expose nasty sexual urges
that will amaze a viewer. This extremely personal approach causes the
performers to become very vulnerable< They’re not fucking for you.
Taylor: Pornographic Confessions
35
indicated that they notice – and are not favorably impressed – when a porn actress
diverges from the standard porn script, for instance by looking directly into the
camera rather than at her partner(s) in the scene. Of course, the direct gaze of the
porn star may be experienced as a challenge to the voyeuristic pleasure of the
viewer, or as a reminder of the presence of a cameraman at whom she really looks,
but when my viewing companions have said ‚she isn’t supposed to look at the
camera‛ at moments such as these, or when they even more frequently comment on
whether the actress is doing a ‚good job‛ or a ‚bad job,‛ this has made me realize
that they do not want an authentic performance or a genuine encounter with the
actress, that they do not want windows into her soul or her sexuality, but a well-
performed adherence to a standard pornographic script. If the direct gaze is any
indication of what she is really thinking, they do not ‚will to know‛ this truth.
of a ‚will to know‛ about pleasure (rather than, more obviously, to have pleasure),
but out of a will to know about female pleasure in particular. Williams convincingly
demonstrates that in contrast to the stag films that preceded it, mainstream hardcore
pornography makes some efforts to problematize and represent female pleasure.
Indeed, men interviewed in Pornified stress that they enjoy pornography because the
women are more enthusiastic and pleased by sex than women are in real life. As
Pamela Paul writes, ‚Of all the requirements for enjoyable pornography, men most
commonly cite the appearance of a woman’s reciprocal pleasure as key.‛41 As
‚Ethan‛ says, for instance: ‚Women in porn tend to act like sex is earth-shattering
positioned before the video begins to view pornography as something
performers do for their own pleasures; they are at heart exhibitionists, not
victims, as governmental discourse would have it. Furthermore, you, the
viewer, are the invader on what is essentially a private act; says Pachard,
‘If you begin to feel that you’re invading their privacy, you are.’ Pachard
appeals to the illicit thrill of voyeurism and yet legitimates pornography as
a private, fully consensual act. (Juffer, 60)
authentic sexuality of the porn stars, or that many viewers accept this. Importantly,
however, it is presented by the producer himself as ‚something different,‛ indicating that
in other porn the actors are not expressing their true sexualities or pursuing their real
fantasies, or are not fucking for themselves but for the director and the viewer. By
presenting this particular video as confessional, there is an acknowledgement that
normally what porn actors are doing is not confessional, or is not a performance of their
own personal fantasies, but those of the intended viewers.
41
Paul, 45.
Foucault Studies, No. 7, pp. 18-44
36
even though in reality, sex isn’t like that all the time. Unfortunately<‛42 This
citation shows that consumers of pornography do not think that pornography
represents reality, even if this fantasy may come to construct their desires and even
their expectations in ‚real life.‛ It also shows that many consumers of pornography
want to see female pleasure represented (even if they know it is faked), and the
pornography industry caters to this desire. Unlike sexual scientists such as Kinsey,
however, the mainstream heterosexual pornography industry that Williams is
discussing did not solicit confessions from women about their pleasures and then go
about trying to capture true or even real female pleasure based on this information.
It did not direct male porn stars to perform the acts that real women (or the female
porn stars themselves) say they like in lieu of the usual anal penetration, fellatio, and
money shots, for instance, which is what we might have expected had Williams’
thesis been true, or had pornography really been participating in the will to know
and to tell the truth about female pleasure. Instead, the acts represented in
mainstream heterosexual pornographic films did not change very much – there is
still a great deal of fellatio, in some numbers this is just about all there is, and very
often it occurs as the climactic scene, compared to far less frequent and shorter
(‚foreplay‛) scenes of cunnilingus (and this usually only in films marketed as
‚couples’ porn‛), while the ‚money shot‛ remains a near-constant. The male
orgasm and not the female orgasm is the conclusion to almost all pornographic
numbers (even in ‚couples’ porn‛), even if now the female stars seem to enjoy
receiving the product of the male orgasm as much as the male stars enjoy producing
it.
today, we might have expected to be the confessional sub-category of porn if ever
there was one.43 In fact, as Lavigne points out, amateur pornography for the most
part emulates the professional mainstream. This suggests that amateur
pornographers with their home videos are not interested in revealing the truths of
their individual sexualities any more than their professional counterparts, but are
instead engaged in performing according to the standards, norms, and expectations
established by the professional pornography into which they are thoroughly
assimilated – as, perhaps, most of us now are. Pornographers, then, whether
professional or amateur, have gone on representing the same things as always, but
now they bother to insist that these acts give women pleasure too. If pornography
produced primarily for men is interested in representing female pleasure, it is not the
Ibid., 14.
43
Julie Lavigne, ‚Érotisme féministe en art ou métapornographie. Le sexe selon Carolee
Schneemann, Annie Sprinkle, et Natacha Merritt,‛ Symposium: Canadian Journal of
Continental Philosophy, 11 (2), (Fall 2007), 364.
No comments:
Post a Comment